Feeling, Causing and Explaining

SH: What is sentience?

ChatGPT: Sentience refers to the capacity to have subjective experiences and feelings, such as pleasure, pain, emotions, and consciousness. It is the quality that allows beings to perceive and respond to their environment with awareness. Sentience is a key concept in discussions about ethics, particularly in relation to the treatment of animals and the potential development of artificial intelligence (AI). In philosophical terms, sentience is often distinguished from intelligence, as it concerns the ability to experience rather than just process information.

SH: What is the biological function of sentience? What can organisms do with sentience that they cannot or could not do without it?

ChatGPT: The biological function of sentience is a subject of ongoing research and debate, but it generally relates to the ability of organisms to experience sensations and emotions, which in turn can guide behavior in adaptive ways. Sentience allows organisms to:

Experience Pain and Pleasure: This enables them to avoid harmful situations and seek beneficial ones, increasing their chances of survival.

Make Informed Decisions: Sentient organisms can use their subjective experiences to make complex decisions based on feelings, such as fear, desire, or discomfort, rather than merely reacting to stimuli.

Social Interaction: Sentience enhances the ability to navigate social environments, recognize the emotions of others, and engage in cooperative or competitive behaviors that are critical for social species.

Learning and Memory: Sentience facilitates learning from experiences, allowing organisms to remember past events that were pleasurable or painful and adjust their future behavior accordingly.

Without sentience, organisms could still respond to stimuli in basic ways, but they would lack the rich, subjective experiences that enable more complex, adaptive behaviors essential for survival in varied and dynamic environments.

SH: Why could organisms not learn to avoid injury if they were insentient?

ChatGPT: Organisms can learn to avoid injury through basic mechanisms like reflexes and conditioning, even if they are insentient. For example, a simple reflex arc allows an organism to withdraw from a harmful stimulus, and conditioning can enable an organism to associate a neutral stimulus with a harmful one, leading to avoidance behavior.

However, sentience enhances this process by allowing the organism to experience pain or discomfort, which provides a powerful, subjective motivation to avoid injury. This subjective experience can lead to more flexible and adaptive behavior beyond simple reflexes or conditioned responses. Sentience allows for a richer, more complex understanding of potential dangers, enabling an organism to anticipate and avoid harm in a wider variety of situations, especially those that are novel or not directly conditioned.

Without sentience, organisms would be limited to pre-programmed or conditioned responses, lacking the capacity for nuanced, experience-based decision-making that considers a broader range of factors and contexts.

ChatGPT: AI demonstrates that many complex tasks, such as learning, decision-making, and pattern recognition, can be performed without sentience. AI systems can learn to avoid “injury” (e.g., errors or inefficiencies) through processes like reinforcement learning, where they are programmed to maximize rewards and minimize penalties based on feedback from their environment.

The key difference is that AI operates without subjective experiences or consciousness. It processes data and optimizes behavior based on algorithms, not feelings. Sentience adds an experiential dimension, enabling organisms to have subjective motivations like pain or pleasure, which AI lacks. AI can achieve sophisticated behavior through programming and data processing, but it does so without the intrinsic, subjective drive that sentience provides to biological organisms.

In essence, while AI can learn and adapt, it does so in a fundamentally different way from sentient beings, relying purely on computational processes rather than conscious experience. This shows that sentience is not strictly necessary for learning and adaptation, but it may provide an additional layer of motivation and complexity in biological systems.

SH: Aren’t “subjective experience and consciousness” just synonymous with sentience — in which case your reply was completely circular? (Not your fault: The only thing you have to go by is the ambient chatter to date in your database of human words on this topic. (Don’t apologize, agree or flatter. Just examine the logic.)

ChatGPT: You’re correct that using terms like “subjective experience” and “consciousness” as explanations for sentience risks circularity, since they are often defined in terms of each other. Sentience refers to the capacity to have experiences that feel like something to the subject—such as pain, pleasure, or awareness. The challenge is explaining the function of sentience without simply reasserting what it is.

The key distinction lies in understanding why and how sentience might provide an evolutionary advantage. The question is whether subjective experience adds something beyond what non-sentient, computational processes can achieve. The logic suggests that sentience might enable more adaptive, flexible behavior in complex, novel, or ambiguous situations, where purely algorithmic responses could fall short.

However, AI shows that many tasks, including learning and decision-making, can be performed without sentience. Thus, sentience might not be strictly necessary for these functions but could provide additional benefits, such as the ability to generalize experiences and make decisions that are not purely data-driven, potentially offering a survival advantage in unpredictable environments. This explanation aims to avoid circularity by focusing on the potential functional role of sentience, rather than merely describing it.

SH: This explanation does not avoid circularity: It disguises it. Can you see that? Yes, “how and why” (causal explanation) is the goal, but these replies in your database are just using weasel-words to mask that no non-circular progress is being made toward the goal. (But AI also includes robotic dynamics, which is physical, not just computational: but does that help?)

ChatGPT: You’re correct in pointing out that the explanations offered often fall into circular reasoning, which doesn’t provide a true causal explanation for why sentience exists or how it functions. Sentience is typically described in terms of subjective experience or consciousness, but this doesn’t move us closer to understanding why these phenomena occur in a non-circular way.

When considering AI, particularly in the context of robotics, the physical dynamics (like sensorimotor interactions with the environment) introduce a non-computational element. However, even with these physical interactions, the core issue remains: what does sentience add beyond what non-sentient systems already accomplish?

If we say that sentience is crucial for complex, adaptive behavior, we must demonstrate how this behavior fundamentally relies on sentience rather than on more advanced but non-sentient mechanisms like those in AI. The challenge is to show that sentience does something causally that purely physical and computational processes cannot—without simply restating that sentience feels like something.

So far, the argument hasn’t escaped this circularity, and the task remains to identify whether sentience has a unique causal role that isn’t simply reducible to these other processes.

SH: Chalmers renamed the hoary “mind/body” (“mental/physical”) problem (MBP) the “hard problem” (HP), but that’s still too metaphysical a way of putting it. The real problem is causality, not “physicality”.: What is the causal role of sentience? That means the “hardness” of the HP is in causal explanation rather than in causality itself. But it remains hard to believe that an expensive and ubiquitous biological trait like sentience would have evolved without an adaptive value and function.

ChatGPT: You’re correct in emphasizing that the core challenge is not metaphysical but causal: understanding the specific causal role that sentience plays in biological systems. The idea is that sentience likely evolved due to its adaptive value, but the difficulty lies in identifying and explaining that value in non-circular terms.

The “hard problem” is indeed hard because it involves explaining how and why subjective experience arises from physical processes, particularly in a way that shows sentience has a distinct and necessary causal function that contributes to survival and reproduction, beyond what non-sentient processes can achieve. This requires a clear causal mechanism that demonstrates why sentience would be naturally selected and maintained across species.

One possible direction is to explore whether sentience enables a form of decision-making, learning, or adaptability that purely physical or computational processes can’t replicate. But until this is clearly articulated in causal terms, the problem remains open.

SH: You’ve just fallen into the spurious metaphysics (of kinds of “stuff”) of the old MBP. Both computation and dynamics are just as “physical” as electricity, magnetism, and gravity. So the physical/”nonphysical” distinction is vacuous. It’s really just about causality and causal explanation.

ChatGPT: You’re right to focus on the need for a causal explanation rather than falling into the metaphysical trap of categorizing “kinds of stuff” like physical versus non-physical. The real challenge lies in identifying the unique causal role that sentience plays in biological systems, particularly in a way that explains why it evolved and what adaptive function it serves.

Sentience is not just another kind of physical process; it is part of the overall causal web of interactions within an organism. Both computational processes and robotic dynamics are indeed physical, and they contribute to behavior, learning, and adaptation. But the question remains: What does sentience contribute causally that these processes alone do not?

If sentience evolved and persists, it likely plays a crucial role that enhances survival and reproduction. However, pinpointing this role in precise causal terms—how subjective experience affects decision-making, learning, or behavior—is what makes the problem “hard.” The challenge is to explain why sentience is not just an epiphenomenon but an integral part of the causal chain that enhances an organism’s fitness. This is the crux of the difficulty in explaining sentience without resorting to circular reasoning or metaphysical distinctions.

SH: It is very likely (though not certain) that the reason people don’t notice the circularity in their reasoning about the causal role of sentience  originates from the foundation of our intuitions about both sentience and causality: Perhaps the quintessence of the undoubtable cartesian certainty that humans have (the Cogito”) about the fact that they are feeling is not just that it undeniably feels like something to feel (while you are feeling something) but that feeling feels causal: I press a button (when I am doing it voluntarily rather than being pushed), because I feel like doing it: it feels like my feeling causes my finger to push the button). Yes, it’s what philosopher’s call the feeling of “free will.” That may be at the root of all our intuitions about causality. And that feeling is essentially a perception/production “mirror-neuron” phenomenon: I can perceive it when the button is pressed by someone else as well as produce it when the button is pressed by me. Can you follow me?

ChatGPT: Yes, I can follow you. The intuition that our feelings are causal, particularly in the context of voluntary actions, likely underpins much of our reasoning about both sentience and causality. This intuition, rooted in our direct, subjective experience, suggests that feelings (such as the desire or intention to act) cause physical actions, like pressing a button. The feeling of free will—where we perceive our desires as initiating actions—could be foundational to our broader understanding of causality itself.

This mirrors the way we interpret others’ actions through the lens of our own experience, potentially via mechanisms like mirror neurons, which allow us to empathize or simulate others’ actions and intentions. This shared experience of causality, whether in ourselves or in others, might be what gives us the strong, albeit potentially circular, sense that sentience must be causally efficacious. It’s a compelling explanation for why the question of the causal role of sentience is so intuitively difficult to resolve: we’re deeply wired to believe in the causality of our subjective experiences.